2.8 Deductive vs. Inductive arguments

LEARNING OBJECTIVES


By the end of this section you will discover:

  • The difference between deductive and inductive arguments.

The concepts of validity and soundness that we have introduced apply only to the class of what are called “deductive arguments”. A deductive argument is an argument whose conclusion is supposed to follow from its premises with absolute certainty, thus leaving no possibility that the conclusion does not follow from the premises.

Deductive Argument: an argument whose conclusion is supposed to follow from its premises with absolute certainty

For a deductive argument to fail to do this is for it to fail as a deductive argument.

In contrast, an inductive argument is an argument whose conclusion is supposed to follow from its premises with a high level of probability, which means that although it is possible that the conclusion does not follow from its premises, it is unlikely that this is the case.

Inductive Argument: an argument whose conclusion is supposed to follow from its premises with a high level of probability

This video should help you understand the differences.

How to Argue – Introduction & Abduction: Crash Course Philosophy #3 

Or watch the video here

 

DEDUCTIVE REASONING INDUCTIVE REASONING
Premises Stated as facts or general principles (“All crows are black”) Statements from observations of specific instances (“The crow on my clothesline is black”)
Conclusion If the premises are arranged logically, the conclusion offers certain knowledge If the premises are compelling the conclusion can lead to a probable hypothesis, but never certainty
Validity If the premises are true the conclusion is guaranteed true If the premises are true the conclusion is probably true

Here is an example of an inductive argument:

Tweets is a healthy, normally functioning bird and since most healthy, normally functioning birds fly, Tweets probably flies.

Notice that the conclusion, Tweets probably flies, contains the word “probably.” This is a clear indicator that the argument is supposed to be inductive, not deductive. Here is the argument in standard form:

  1. Tweets is a healthy, normally functioning bird
  2. Most healthy, normally functioning birds fly
  3. Therefore, Tweets probably flies

Given the information provided by the premises, the conclusion does seem to be well supported. That is, the premises do give us a strong reason for accepting the conclusion. This is true even though we can imagine a scenario in which the premises are true and yet the conclusion is false. For example, suppose that we added the following premise:

Tweets is 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph.

Were we to add that premise, the conclusion would no longer be supported by the premises, since any bird that is 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph, is not a kind of bird that can fly. That information leads us to believe that Tweets is an ostrich or emu, which are not kinds of birds that can fly. As this example shows, inductive arguments are defeasible arguments since by adding further information or premises to the argument, we can overturn (defeat) the verdict that the conclusion is well-supported by the premises. Inductive arguments—whose premises give us a strong, even if defeasible, reason for accepting the conclusion— are called, unsurprisingly, strong inductive arguments. In contrast, an inductive argument that does not provide a strong reason for accepting the conclusion are called weak inductive arguments.

Whereas strong inductive arguments are defeasible, valid deductive arguments are not. Suppose that instead of saying that most birds fly, premise 2 said that all birds fly.

  1. Tweets is a healthy, normally function bird.
  2. All healthy, normally functioning birds can fly.
  3. Therefore, Tweets can fly.

This is a valid argument and since it is a valid argument, there are no further premises that we could add that could overturn the argument’s validity. (True, premise 2 is false, but as we have seen that is irrelevant to determining whether an argument is valid.) Even if we were to add the premise that Tweets is 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph, it does not overturn the validity of the argument. As soon as we use the universal generalization, “all healthy, normally function birds can fly,” then when we assume that premise is true and add that Tweets is a healthy, normally functioning bird, it has to follow from those premises that Tweets can fly. This is true even if we add that Tweets is 6 ft tall because then what we have to imagine (in applying our informal test of validity) is a world in which all birds, including those that are 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph, can fly.

Although inductive arguments are an important class of argument that are commonly used every day in many contexts, logic texts tend not to spend as much time with them since we have not agreed upon standard of evaluating them. In contrast, there is an agreed upon standard of evaluation of deductive arguments. We have already seen what that is; it is the concept of validity. In chapter 2 we will learn some precise, formal methods of evaluating deductive arguments. There are no such agreed upon formal methods of evaluation for inductive arguments. This is an area of ongoing research in philosophy. In chapter 3 we will revisit inductive arguments and consider some ways to evaluate inductive arguments.

 

 

Works Cited

CrashCourse, director. How to Argue – Induction & Abduction: Crash Course Philosophy #3. YouTube, YouTube, 22 Feb. 2016, https://youtu.be/-wrCpLJ1XAw

License

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License

PPSC PHI 1011: The Philosopher's Quest by Daniel G. Shaw, Ph.D. is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book