APPENDIX: Common Logical Fallacies

Daniel G. Shaw and Ph.D.

Assessing the legitimacy of arguments embedded in ordinary language is rather like diagnosing whether a living human being has any broken bones. Only the internal structure matters, but it is difficult to see through the layers of flesh that cover it. … The informal fallacies considered here are patterns of reasoning that are obviously incorrect. [They often] … clearly fail to provide adequate reason for believing the truth of their conclusions. Although they are often used in attempts to persuade people by non-logical means, only the unwary, the predisposed, and the gullible are apt to be fooled by their illegitimate appeals. Many of them were identified by medieval and renaissance logicians, whose Latin names for them have passed into common use. It’s worthwhile to consider the structure, offer an example, and point out the invalidity of each of them in turn. (Gabriel Camacho, Introduction to Philosophy, OER.)

Composition

Inferring that something is true of the whole from the fact that it is true of some part of the whole. This is the opposite of the fallacy of division.
  • “The universe must be caused by something because everything in the universe has a cause.”
  • “If one runner in a race runs faster, he or she can win. Therefore, if every runner in the race runs faster, they can all win.”
  • “The legs of this chair are made of wood, so the whole chair must be made of wood.”

Note that this fallacy moves from the part to the whole by assuming that because something is true about a part of a set it must be true about the whole of the set.

Division

A fallacy of division is an informal fallacy that occurs when one reasons that something that is true for a whole must also be true of all or some of its parts.  This is the opposite of the fallacy of composition.

  • The United States is the richest country in the world. Therefore, everyone in the United States must be rich and live well.
  • Women in the United States are paid less than men. Therefore, my mom must make less money than my dad.
  • Football is the most popular sport in America.  Sally is an American, so she must love football.

Note that this fallacy moves from the whole to the part by assuming that because something is true about an entire set it must be true about each particular in the set.

Appeal to Pity (argumentum ad misericordiam)

Turning this on its head, an appeal to pity tries to win acceptance by pointing out the unfortunate consequences that will otherwise fall upon the speaker and others, for whom we would then feel sorry.

  • I am a single parent, solely responsible for the financial support of my children.
  • If you give me this traffic ticket, I will lose my license and be unable to drive to work.
  • If I cannot work, my children and I will become homeless and may starve to death.
  • Therefore, you should not give me this traffic ticket.

Again, the conclusion may be false (that is, perhaps I should be given the ticket) even if the premises are all true, so the argument is fallacious.

Appeal to Emotion (argumentum ad populum)

In a more general fashion, the appeal to emotion relies upon emotively charged language to arouse strong feelings that may lead an audience to accept its conclusion:

  • As all clear-thinking residents of our fine state have already realized, the Governor’s plan for financing public education is nothing but the bloody-fanged wolf of socialism cleverly disguised in the harmless sheep’s clothing of concern for children.
  • Therefore, the Governor’s plan is bad public policy.

The problem here is that although the flowery language of the premise might arouse strong feelings in many members of its intended audience, the widespread occurrence of those feelings has nothing to do with the truth of the conclusion.

Appeal to Authority (argumentum ad verecundiam)

In an appeal to authority, the opinion of someone famous or accomplished in another area of expertise is supposed to guarantee the truth of a conclusion. Thus, for example:

  • Federal Reserve Chair Alan Greenspan believes that spiders are insects.
  • Therefore, spiders are insects.

As a pattern of reasoning, this is clearly mistaken: no proposition must be true because some individual (however talented or successful) happens to believe it. Even in areas where they have some special knowledge or skill, expert authorities could be mistaken; we may accept their testimony as inductive evidence but never as deductive proof of the truth of a conclusion. Personality is irrelevant to the truth.

Ad Hominem Argument

The mirror image of the appeal to authority is the ad hominem argument, in which we are encouraged to reject a proposition because it is the stated opinion of someone regarded as disreputable in some way. This can happen in several different ways, but all involve the claim that the proposition must be false because of who believes it to be true:

  • Harold maintains that the legal age for drinking beer should be 18 instead of 21.
  • But we all know that Harold . . .
  • . . . dresses funny and smells bad. or
  • . . . is 19 years old and would like to drink legally or
  • . . . believes that the legal age for voting should be 21, not 18 or
  • . . . doesn’t understand the law any better than the rest of us.
  • Therefore, the legal age for drinking beer should be 21 instead of 18.

Two common forms of Ad Hominum are Ad Hominum Abusive and Ad Hominum Circumstantial.

Ad Hominum Abusive – This is where the person is directly attacked for her character, her habits, and even her gender (i.e. This is why a woman shouldn’t do a man’s job.)

Ad Hominem – Circumstantial – Usually this argument attacks a position by appealing to the vested interests of the person who holds the position. Examples: “You can hardly convince me that increases in the military budget are desirable when I happen to know that you work in a munitions factory.” or “Of course, you believe that! You’re a Republican.”

In any of its varieties, the ad hominem fallacy asks us to adopt a position on the truth of a conclusion for no better reason than that someone believes its opposite. But a proposition that a person believes can nevertheless be true (and the intended conclusion false) even if the person is unsavory or has a stake in the issue or holds inconsistent beliefs or shares a common flaw with us. Again, personality is irrelevant to the truth.

Appeal to Ignorance (argumentum ad ignoratiam)

An appeal to ignorance proposes that we accept the truth of a proposition unless an opponent can prove otherwise. Thus, for example:

  • No one has conclusively proven that there is no intelligent life on the moons of Jupiter.
  • Therefore, there is intelligent life on the moons of Jupiter.

But, of course, the absence of evidence against a proposition is not enough to secure its truth. What we don’t know could nevertheless be so.

False Cause (post hoc)

The fallacy of false cause infers the presence of a causal connection simply because events appear to occur in correlation or (in the post hoc, ergo propter hoc variety) in temporal succession.

  • The moon was full on Thursday evening.
  • On Friday morning I overslept.
  • Therefore, the full moon caused me to oversleep.

Sometimes evidence adequately supports the conclusion that a causal relationship does exist, but these fallacies clearly are not enough.  They do not fully demonstrate causality.

False Analogy

A type of informal fallacy or a persuasive technique in which the fact that two things are alike in one respect leads to the invalid conclusion that they must be alike in some other respect.  For example:

  • A pocket watch is complex, and it’s clear that it must have been designed intelligently by a watchmaker. Living beings and the world are similarly complex. Thus, they must also be the product of intelligent design.
  • An addiction to drugs or alcohol can completely ruin someone’s life. If you play too many video games and get addicted, you’re going to ruin your life too.
  • Running the country is no different from running a business. It’s irresponsible to keep burying the nation in deeper and deeper debt.

Begging the Question or Circular Reasoning

Begging the question is the fallacy of using the conclusion of an argument as one of the premises offered in its own support. Although this often happens in an implicit or disguised fashion, an explicit version would look like this:

  • All dogs are mammals.
  • All mammals have hair.
  • Since animals with hair bear live young, dogs bear live young.
  • But all animals that bear live young are mammals.
  • Therefore, all dogs are mammals.

Unlike the other fallacies we’ve considered, begging the question involves an argument (or chain of arguments) that is formally valid: if its premises (including the first) are true, then the conclusion must be true. The problem is that this valid argument doesn’t really provide support for the truth in its conclusion; we can’t use it unless we have already granted that.

Red Herring

A red herring is a logical fallacy in which irrelevant information is presented alongside relevant information, distracting attention from that relevant information. This may be done intentionally or unintentionally. A red herring is one of the most commonly used fallacies, especially when an arguer has a weak case.

  • “I understand you want to know what happened at the embassy. What is really important is to talk about whether the government has enough cash flow to stay open through the month.”
  • “Unfortunately, we have to lay off 5% of the workforce. It’s important for us to note that the product we create is exceptionally flawless and we thank our manufacturing department for that.”
  • “Why are you pulling me over for speeding? Shouldn’t you be out catching the real criminals? Someone could be robbing a bank as we speak!”

Equivocation

The fallacy of equivocation occurs when a key term or phrase in an argument is used in an ambiguous way, with one meaning in one portion of the argument and then another meaning in another portion of the argument.

  • “Man is the only intelligent animal on the planet. And, since a woman is not a man, we can say that women are not intelligent.”
  • Laws imply lawgivers. There are laws of nature. Therefore there must be a cosmic lawgiver.
  • Sarah is not an ethical person. It’s so hard to get her to do anything; her work ethic is so bad.

False Dichotomy

A false dichotomy (or, false dilemma) presents a choice between two mutually exclusive options, implying that there are no other options. One option is clearly worse than the other, making the choice seem obvious.

  • Vote for me or live through four more years of higher taxes.
  • America: Love it or leave it.
  • Would you rather pursue your passion or be stuck in a 9-to-5 job?
  • You can look cool in your clothes, or you can look like a loser.

Wishful Thinking (the Is…Ought fallacy)

This fallacy assumes that something Is true because one really thinks it Ought to be true.

  • Of course, the soul is immortal. If it were not, then we would all be mere specks of dust in cosmic time.
  • Angels do exist. It makes me feel better to think they are with me, so I’m justified in saying they are.
  • A personal relationship with God will change your life.

License

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License

APPENDIX: Common Logical Fallacies by Daniel G. Shaw and Ph.D. is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book